Greetings from Toronto, where I gave some talks and had a great time with the archaeologists at the University of Toronto.
Actually, I don't particularly like epistemology. |
I just read American
Anthropologist’s 2012 review article on archaeological publications in 2011 (Hauser 2012). I came away confused about author
Mark Hauser’s epistemology. I can’t seem to translate his approach into my own
understanding of social science concepts of explanation and causality. Like
many archaeologists, Hauser seems reluctant to discuss these things clearly and
explicitly, leaving readers to puzzle them out from fragmentary and cryptic phrases.
I was particularly confused by two statements in
Hauser’s paper:
· “addressing long-standing questions about agriculture
with new data require a shift from
causality to explanations of process in specified contexts.” (p. 185)
· “One major shift was a general move from the search for causes to explanation of
cultivation, domestication, and farming.” (p. 186).
I find this puzzling, because to me, explanation means
finding the cause for something. So what does Hauser mean by a shift from
causality to explanation? His phrasing suggests that causality is the old and
bad way of looking at things, while explanation is a new and good approach.
This statement might give a clue:
· “interpretive narratives find their expressions in
situated explanations—a grounding in the messy idiosyncrasies of
evidence—context—culture—history that run counter to more ambitious
inclinations to craft explanatory models of history at larger scales.” (p.184)
Leaving aside the confusing conjunction of four words
with hyphens, this statement suggests that Hauser is advocating explanation at
a small scale. But does he mean a smaller spatial scale (we should concentrate
on explaining a particular event in a particular place, not a large-scale
spatial process like an empire or world system)? Or does he mean a smaller
analytical scale (we should explain this particular household, and not
households in general)? In my view, we need to explain things at a variety of spatial
and analytical scales, and it doesn’t make much sense to prefer one level over another.
It depends on the research question one is asking.
To me, talk of explanations at different scales
suggests the concepts of proximate and ultimate causality. These concepts were
first articulated in biology by Ernst Mayr (Mayr
1961). Proximate causes concern immediate factors such as ontogeny, and
ultimate causes produce evolutionary explanations. While new work in biology
has complicated this dichotomy, the basic distinction remains important in that
field (Laland et al. 2011).
The proximate-ultimate distinction in causality is
also important in the social sciences:
· “ultimate explanations are concerned with why a
behavior exists, and proximate explanations are concerned with how it works.”(Scott-Phillips et al. 2011:38)
Some writers parallel the approach of Laland et al in
biology by advocating a more complex concept of social causation, but retaining
the basic insight of the proximate/ultimate distinction. John Gerring (2005, 2012), for example, talks about “causal
distance”: how far is the cause from the event it generates? Lieberson and Lynn
(2002) use the phrases “underlying
conditions” and “precipitating conditions” for these concepts.
But I don’t think this is the kind of thing Hauser has
in mind, since he seems hostile to (or at least dismissive of) the concept of
causality.
OK, let’s step back and look at what kinds of
explanatory models are available in the social sciences (and, by extension, in
archaeology). I always return to Charles Tilly for this kind of thing. I’m not
a very good abstract thinker, and Tilly clarifies many epistemological issues
in terms I can understand. According to Tilly, five explanatory strategies are
available in the social and historical sciences. The following is my
paraphrasing of: Tilly (2001:365) and
Tilly and Goodin (2006:12-13); see also
Tilly (2008). The text following *** are
my own comments.
1.
Skepticism.
The world is too complex to explain. *** I think this would be the strong
postmodern position.
2.
Law-seeking accounts. Social life is said to exhibit empirical regularities
that at their highest level take the form of laws; explanation then consists of
subsuming particular cases under broadly validated empirical generalizations or
even universal laws. *** This is “logical positivism,” a framework associated
with Carl Hempel. Binford and the new archaeologists promoted this approach to
explanation, EVEN THOUGH IT HAD ALREADY BEEN DISCREDITED FOR SOCIAL SCIENCE BY
PHILOSOPHERS OF SCIENCE! This was one of the biggest mistakes of Binford and
the new archaeology, and it set archaeological epistemology back for decades!
3.
Propensity accounts. Social units are seen as self-directing, whether driven by emotions,
motives, interests, rational choices, genes, or something else. Explanation
then consists of reconstructing the state of the social unit—for example, an
individual’s beliefs at a given point in time and space—and plausibly relating
its actions to that state. *** Most
examples of propensity accounts follow methodological individualism, or the
standard model in economics that says social phenomenon can be explained by the
goals, decisions, and behavior of individuals. But other individual-level
approaches, such as phenomenology, probably fit here as well.
4.
Systemic explanations. Particular features of social life are explained by
specifying their connections with putative larger entities: societies,
cultures, mentalities, capitalist systems, and the like. Explanation then
consists of locating elements within systems. Functional explanation is a
subcategory of systemic explanations. *** This includes both cultural
explanations and explanations invoking large structural features such as social
classes or world systems.
5.
Mechanism-based accounts. This approach claims that explanation consists of
identifying in particular social phenomena reliable causal mechanisms and
processes of general scope. Causal mechanisms are events that alter relations
among some set of elements. Processes are frequent (but not universal)
combinations and sequences of causal mechanisms. *** This is the way I think
about explanation and causality. To explain an event is to identify the
mechanisms responsible for bringing about that event. There is a BIG literature
outside of anthropology on causal mechanisms. Some good starting points are: (Bunge 2004),
(Hedström and Ylikoski 2010), (Sampson 2011), and various works by Tilly, e.g.
(Tilly 2008). Or check out Daniel Little’s blog, “Understanding Society” and search it for mechanisms.
When I started thinking about Hauser’s puzzling
statements on causality and explanation, I thought Tilly’s scheme of the five explanatory
approaches would clarify the situation, but now I’m not so sure. I still can’t
figure out what Hauser’s explanatory position is, or how he can oppose the
terms causality and explanation. I have almost given up trying to understand
archaeological writing in this genre, that might be called “postmodern-light.” I guess I will just have to admit defeat here.
My broader point is that archaeologists need to
discuss epistemology more frequently, more explicitly, and more in tune with
the relevant social science literature. Our own field has a rather poor track
record in this area, and cultural anthropology is not much better. If this
stuff is new to you, check out Tilly or Bunge or some of the other sources
below. When I find myself in a conceptual difficulty, I often ask myself, “what
would Tilly say about this?” Maybe you should ask that question too.
Bunge, Mario
2004 How
Does It Work?: The Search for Explanatory Mechanisms. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34(2):182-210.
Gerring, John
2005 Causation:
A Unified Framework for the Social Sciences. Journal of Theoretical Politics 17:163-198.
2012 Social Science Methodology: A Unified
Framework. 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press, New York.
Hauser, Mark W.
2012 The
Year in Review, Archaeololgy: Messy Data, Ordered Questions. American Anthroologist 114(2):184-195.
Hedström, Peter and Petri Ylikoski
2010 Causal
Mechanisms in the Social Sciences. Annual
Review of Sociology 36:49-67.
Laland, Kevin N., Kim Sterelny, John
Odling-Smee, William Hoppitt, and Tobias Uller
2011 Cause
and Effect in Biology Revisited: Is Mayr's Proximate-Ultimate Dichotomy Still
Useful? Science 334:1512-1515.
Lieberson, Stanley and Freda B. Lynn
2002 Barking
up the Wrong Branch: Scientific Alternatives to the Current Model of
Sociological Science. Annual Review of
Sociology 28:1-19.
Mayr, Ernst
1961 Cause
and Effect in Biology. Science
134:1501-1506.
Sampson, Robert J.
2011 Neighborhood
Effects, Causal Mechanisms and the Social Structure of the City. In Analytical
Sociology and Social Mechanisms, edited by Pierre Demeulenaere, pp.
227-249. Cambridge Universitiy Press, New York.
Scott-Phillips, Thomas C., Thomas E.
Dickins, and Stuart A. West
2011 Evolutionary
Theory and the Ultimate–Proximate Distinction in the Human Behavioral Sciences.
Perspectives on Psychological Science
6(1):38-47.
Tilly, Charles
2001 Relational
Origins of Inequality. Anthropological
Theory 1(3):355-372.
2008 Explaining Social Processes. Paradigm
Publishers, Boulder, CO.
Tilly, Charles and Robert E. Goodin
2006 It
Depends. In Oxford Handbook of Contextual Political Analysis, edited by Robert
E. Goodin and Charles Tilly, pp. 3-32. Oxford University Press, New York.
5 comments:
A couple of points:
1. Terms like causation and mechanism smack of the physical sciences, without considering how those sciences may have moved on since Newton. There's a lot going on in quantum physics and so on that doesn't make its way to the social sciences. So let's not pretend to be on their level.
2. Each social phenomenon is likely to be multi-causal, and not only in a proximate/ultimate cause way. This is what the Annales school and time perspectivism have taught us. This implies it's more interesting to look at causation using a systemic approach, since these can bring together the different causal factors in a coherent framework.
3. There is a bias towards propensity and mechanism based accounts, because they describe how things work within a system. Whereas systemic explanations seem much more tedious and of unclear value. But if one accepts the idea of multiple, interacting causes it is impossible to speak of a closed system. The only way propensity and mechanis accounts can work, in my view, is when quite artificial boundaries are set up that specify precisely what has to be accounted for.
So, while I think it's possible to do something with causation, I also believe it's near value-less if not put within a wider systemic framework. Actually, I still think Childe has the best ideas so far about this in archaeology. Doesn't say much good about epistemology in our profession, probably. Though of course the empirical work is excellent today.
@Marcus- I would suggest reading some of the social science literature on causal mechanisms before dismissing the concept for archaeology.
I did browse through it at one point, primarily through the Understanding Society blog. It didn't entice me to look further. The thrust seems to be to replace the larger social categories (early civilisations, capitalism etc.) with a focus on social mechanisms. In my view that impoverishes analysis if one takes it as the central core of one's method.
Not saying it's useless, especially in modern contexts, I'm just more of a systemic guy.
"Terms like causation and mechanism smack of the physical sciences"
But where did the physical sciences got those words from initially? From a pre-scientific understanding of everyday life... so they seem like a good place to start, when you're trying to understand the everyday life of the past.
Neuroskeptic, I'm definitely not against archaeology learning anything from the physical sciences. But their ideas about causality are a little more developed than in the social sciences, I would say. We could learn from that, actually, if we got through the mathematics.
Post a Comment